PHL100-T0401-SUM#2-MOSSMAN-PATRICK
In book 1 of The Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle argues that The Good for a human is not a state of being, but instead virtuous activity. Aristotle first states that each field of human accomplishment seeks some sort of end. He continues that ends can be desired as a means to further ends, simply as ends in themselves, or both. Accordingly, the final end, The Good that is being ultimately sought, would be that which is the end to which other ends are directed towards, and is desired solely for itself (NE. 1097a15-1097b, pp.10). Aristotle then states that The Good would be self-sufficient, and defines a thing as self-sufficient when it, on its own, makes life so fulfilled nothing more can be meaningfully added.
…show more content…
This is because The Good and Happiness have been ill-defined so far, having only outlined that Happiness must be what is finally sought. Without knowing the nature of either in sufficient detail, it is meaningless to define one as the other (NE. 1097b20-25, pp.11). Aristotle then posits that this nature could be found if we determined the function of mankind, as The Good has been thought to reside in the function of a given activity or thing. Firstly, Aristotle sets out to prove that Man has a function at all. He begins by referring to various jobs, such as carpenters and tanners as having functions, and then uses eyes, feet, and other body parts as similar examples. It follows for Aristotle that mankind similarly has a function. Here, It should be remembered that Aristotle’s ‘function’ is something which is unique to its possessor. Next, Aristotle begins to narrow down what Man’s function is. He discards that simple life and growth is Man’s function, as plants do the same, and he discards that living a perceptive life is Man’s function, as animals do the same. What Aristotle finds remains after this narrowing is that living life in accordance with reason, specifically the activity of reasoning must be the function of mankind(NE. 1097b25-1098a5, …show more content…
To begin, Aristotle points out that we can qualify something as a simply itself, or a ‘good’ instance of itself when excellence is achieved. The example is given that lyre player plays the lyre, and a good lyre player plays well. Aristotle elaborates that an function is in accordance with The Good when it is performed in accordance with its appropriate virtue. In this case, recalling that the function of a man is activity of the soul implying a rational principle, it can be seen that the function of a Good man is to do so with excellence and rationality, the chosen virtue (NE. 1098a5-10, pp.11-12). Aristotle then concludes that Goodness is the activity of the soul exhibiting virtue. Aristotle then links this back to his earlier argument on Happiness, saying that if this is done throughout one’s life, happiness will be achieved, implying that this is due to the link between the final end and The Good. Here it can be seen that Aristotle has subtly reversed the assumed relationship between the two, now showing that living The Good life will bring Happiness, not simply that Happiness is The Good life (NE. 1098a10-20,
In Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle argues that the human good is the soul’s activity that expresses virtue. Aristotle concludes this from an invalid argument. On the one hand I do agree that the activity expressing virtue is a requirement for the human good. But on the other hand, I insist that the human good is a state and not an action. By modifying this argument, I believe we can reach a new conclusion that will help us better understand what Aristotle meant by these concepts.
The purpose of Aristotle’s function argument is to determine the function of the human being. The role of the argument in Aristotle’s investigation is to identify the true human good, which in essence, will help humans to live well and happy lives. He uses rationality as a basis for his arguments, stating that the characteristic is unique to human life because no other living organisms are able to act and think in accordance with reason. Therefore cannot live, to the same extent, the happy and function-fulfilling life that humans are able to. It is useful to understand the concept of function as it applies to human beings because without it, we would not understand how it connects with our virtues and human good.
In Book I of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle brings up the idea that in order to discover the human good we must first develop a certain understanding and identify the function of a human being. Aristotle’s function argument is brought up through his belief that the human function is rational activity, meaning that our good as human beings is rational activity performed fine because this is what leads to living well. The good Aristotle tries to get across can be seen in many different forms depending on how it is viewed, because of the idea that the main function of anything is to reach a final end, the final end is considered the good. “The end of medicine is health, that of shipbuilding, a ship, that of military science, victory…” (Nicomachean,
o Ex. Marriage After marrying someone, you must have sex that night to legitimatize the marriage. This physical act is what helps you to experience god. Homework Assignment: Aristotle- Nicomachean Ethics Book 1 • Section One: o All things are done in aim of the good…therefore, the good has been at the aim of everyone actions o The end goal of each persons action differ depending on the activity they are pursuing o Activities can be the ends of the actions, but the ends can also be apart from the activities
According to Aristotle, an individual can achieve happiness only by realizing all the works and activities in accordance with reason throughout his lifetime. He claimed that happiness consists in cultivating and exercising virtue and it is the ultimate purpose of human existence, as stated in his work Nicomachean Ethics “He is happy who lives in accordance with complete virtue and is sufficiently equipped with external goods, not for some chance period but throughout a complete life”. However, such Aristotelian concept of happiness inevitably contradicts the understanding of history as development which maintains that fulfilling the work of human exceeds the limits of an individual and thus can only be achieved in the course of history. Three
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics begins by exploring ‘the good’. Book I argues that, unlike other goods, “happiness appears to be something complete and self-sufficient, and is, therefore, the end of actions” (10:1097b20-21). In other words, happiness is the ultimate good. But how does one achieve happiness? Aristotle formulates this in the context of work, since for all things, from artists to horses, “the good and the doing it well seem to be in the work” (10:1097b27-28).
Within Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, he considers humanity and its relationship with moral virtue. By the end of this essay, I will have summarized how Aristotle sees virtue as something that can be improved through repetition and what sort of ideology is required for an action to be considered virtuous. Also, I will address how one may disagree with Aristotle’s views on how a person learns to become virtuous, thinking that the concept of virtue must be precisely defined rather than as free-formed as Aristotle understands it. Following that counterargument, I shall refute it by explaining how a satisfactory childhood impresses society’s code of conduct upon a youth and how a youth learns how to apply that code of conduct through trial and error.
Many classical philosophers have given their voice to the nature of human life and what entails its climax. The very nature of human beings has been investigated, broadly, to establish a comprehensive understanding often pegged on morality. Yet, such thoughts have prompted diverse viewpoints with accompanying grounds or reasons. Happiness is an unending topic of discussion in philosophy. This paper explores the similarities and differences in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics and John Stuart Mill’s Utilitarianism to coin a position in whether or not happiness is the ultimate end that human society aspires to acquire.
In Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, the concept of happiness is introduced as the ultimate good one can achieve in life as well as the ultimate goal of human existence. As Aristotle goes on to further define happiness, one can see that his concept is much different from the 21st-century view. Aristotelian happiness can be achieved through choosing to live the contemplative life, which would naturally encompass moralistic virtue. This differs significantly from the modern view of happiness, which is heavily reliant on material goods. To a person in the 21st-century, happiness is simply an emotional byproduct one experiences as a result of acquiring material goods.
According to Aristotle, everything we do in life, we do for the sake of some good, or at least something we perceive to be good. We call an act good if it satisfies a certain need. The satisfaction of this need is then considered good if it is a means for satisfying some further need, and this in turn is good if it will satisfy still another need. Sooner or later this process reaches a point where it is no longer a means for some further end but is an end in itself. This final end is what Aristotle means by the chief good.
as being considered as happiness, as they often by nature accompany stipulated happiness as the activity of virtue. This Aristotle goes on to consider, 1) the general nature of the good character and good action, then 2) the principal moral virtues, the virtues of that part of man which can follow the plan laid down by reason, then 3) the virtue of intellect (Shimomissé). He also examines the ideal life or the idea of the life of in agreement with virtue. Aristotle notes that all of us possess the good character by nature in the form of power, but it has to be sufficiently developed to an actuality by practice. So what we have to do is to develop a habit of doing virtuous acts without any thematic consciousness.
In short knowing and doing are in the same line. In knowing the truth your virtues will ultimately be guided by this knowledge. The “telos” or ultimate goal of human life for Aristotle is to attain “happiness”. “Happiness” here is does not mean the common meaning which we use everyday but it is more synonymous to the war “eudaimonia” which means to be in a state of being that is in good spirit. This emphasis that happiness is not just a temporary thing but a permanent outlook on life which means that they only way for us to truly know whether we have had a happy life is when we die.
In order to do this, we need to 'know thyself ' and become as learned as we can, knowing the good for all, while also being humble. We are all naturally good people, so we must promote the good in the world. According to Aristotle, however, happiness, his goal for all humans is not that easy to obtain. He claims that "happiness is a certain sort of activity of the soul in accord with virtue (Aristotle, p.12). On the Aristotelian model of how to obtain happiness, it deals a great deal with the issue of particulars.
Aristotle refers to the soul as a part of the human body and what its role is in pursuing true happiness
For Aristotle, happiness is the end and purpose of human existence. To pursue happiness is to go for telos. Happiness is neither pleasure nor virtue, but an exercise of virtue. Happiness cannot be achieved until the end of one’s life. Hence, it is a goal not a temporary state.